Why retribution is immoral




















The concept of retribution is based on an archaic sense of ethics which is not only irrational, but goes so far as to compound the very suffering that it is intended to prevent. This entry was posted on June 11, at pm and is filed under Ethics , Utilitarianism.

You can follow any responses to this entry through the RSS 2. You can leave a response , or trackback from your own site.

Granted, that comes with its own problem corruption , but for the sake of argument, let us ignore that. This would be in addition to a jail sentence. There must be some reason evolution has left us with the instinct to seek revenge.

My belief is, that reason is a good one. It seems to me that the emotional reaction to crime is the primary reason we bother to punish people for committing it.

Your first proposition sounds like a good idea. That would actually have a positive effect on society. Regarding your second point: That reason probably is a good one, but only with respect to evolution; that is, revenge probably gives some sort of evolutionary advantage. The feelings are petty because the victim gains nothing by killing the murderer. The only benefit that the victim gets out of the death penalty is that it might make him feel better.

There are no concrete advantages. But how does this relate to the moral status of punishment and retribution? My thesis in this essay is that the desire for retribution only does unnecessary harm. In my ethical system buddhism killing is wrong. In some buddhist schools there is an exception though…. Some schools of thought say it may be done, but under strict conditions: it must be done out of compassion for the killer, who would otherwise suffer bad karmic consequences , and only if there are no other ways to prevent the crime.

He has taken this burden on his shoulders to help the killer on his way to enlightment. A death penalty for a convicted murderer does not meet even a single one of these conditions.

It is completely unnecessary and done with the wrong motives. Therefore it will only lead to negative consequences for those involved. Most people do not feel better after a revenge — And even if it does them make feel better, must the legal system do this? I think the world would look better with less revenge, not with more.

This is still further evidence that retribution is a bad idea. The right thing to do is to kill the killer, and suffer the consequences yourself? It seems like that is one of the most altruistic things you can do. The interesting and to me convincing aspects of the karmic thinking are: — causes will lead to effects.

There are no causes without effects and vice versa. Good deeds will give an effect and bad deeds like wise — the killer cannot escape from his punishment. Therefore it is not necessary to take revenge, he will get his punishment anyway. In the case of someone who kills for a greater good prevention of even worse things I think both karmic paths are not completed.

Such a path consists of a subject someone who performs the deed , an object against who the action is done , an intention, an action and a effect. The main argument that retribution is immoral is that it is just a sanitised form of vengeance. Scenes of howling mobs attacking prison vans containing those accused of murder on their way to and from court, or chanting aggressively outside prisons when an offender is being executed, suggest that vengeance remains a major ingredient in the public popularity of capital punishment.

But just retribution, designed to re-establish justice, can easily be distinguished from vengeance and vindictiveness. The Victorian legal philosopher James Fitzjames Stephens thought vengeance was an acceptable justification for punishment.

Punishment, he thought, should be inflicted:. But the issue of the execution of innocent persons is also a problem for the retribution argument - if there is a serious risk of executing the innocent then one of the key principles of retribution - that people should get what they deserve and therefore only what they deserve - is violated by the current implementation of capital punishment in the USA, and any other country where errors have taken place.

It's argued that retribution is used in a unique way in the case of the death penalty. Crimes other than murder do not receive a punishment that mimics the crime - for example rapists are not punished by sexual assault, and people guilty of assault are not ceremonially beaten up.

Camus and Dostoevsky argued that the retribution in the case of the death penalty was not fair, because the anticipatory suffering of the criminal before execution would probably outweigh the anticipatory suffering of the victim of their crime.

Others argue that the retribution argument is flawed because the death penalty delivers a 'double punishment'; that of the execution and the preceding wait, and this is a mismatch to the crime.

Many offenders are kept 'waiting' on death row for a very long time; in the USA the average wait is 10 years. In Japan, the accused are only informed of their execution moments before it is scheduled. The result of this is that each day of their life is lived as if it was their last. Some lawyers argue that capital punishment is not really used as retribution for murder, or even consistently for a particular kind of murder.

They argue that, in the USA at least, only a small minority of murderers are actually executed, and that imposition of capital punishment on a "capriciously selected random handful" of offenders does not amount to a consistent programme of retribution. Since capital punishment is not operated retributively, it is inappropriate to use retribution to justify capital punishment.

This argument would have no value in a society that applied the death penalty consistently for particular types of murder. Some people who believe in the notion of retribution are against capital punishment because they feel the death penalty provides insufficient retribution.

They argue that life imprisonment without possibility of parole causes much more suffering to the offender than a painless death after a short period of imprisonment. Another example is the planner of a suicide bombing - execution might make that person a martyr, and therefore would be a lesser retribution than life imprisonment. The death penalty doesn't seem to deter people from committing serious violent crimes.

The thing that deters is the likelihood of being caught and punished. The general consensus among social scientists is that the deterrent effect of the death penalty is at best unproven. In a survey was conducted for the UN to determine the relation between the death penalty and homicide rates. This was then updated in It concluded:. Such proof is unlikely to be forthcoming. The evidence as a whole still gives no positive support to the deterrent hypothesis.

The key to real and true deterrence is to increase the likelihood of detection, arrest and conviction. NB: It's actually impossible to test the deterrent effect of a punishment in a rigorous way, as to do so would require knowing how many murders would have been committed in a particular state if the law had been different during the same time period.

Even if capital punishment did act as a deterrent, is it acceptable for someone to pay for the predicted future crimes of others? This isn't true - if people are randomly picked up off the street and punished as scapegoats the only consequence is likely to be that the public will be frightened to go out. To make a scapegoat scheme effective it would be necessary to go through the appearance of a legitimate legal process and to present evidence which convinced the public that the person being punished deserved their punishment.

While some societies have operated their legal systems on the basis of fictional evidence and confessions extracted by torture, the ethical objections to such a system are sufficient to render the argument in the second paragraph pointless. Statistics show that the death penalty leads to a brutalisation of society and an increase in murder rate. In the USA, more murders take place in states where capital punishment is allowed.

In , the murder rate in states where the death penalty has been abolished was 4. In states where the death penalty is used, the figure was 5. These calculations are based on figures from the FBI.

Should Philosophers Get Political? Truth and Progress in Philosophy. Ai Weiwei: How Censorship Works. A Deep Dive into Democracy. Nietzsche, Schmitt, and the Alt-Right. The Lifespan of a Genre. Envisioning Eastern Hegemony.

Because You Are, I Am. Watered-down Philosophy for Tech Bros. Nozick, Libertarianism, and Philosophy. The Limits of Medical Consent. Defense of Transracialism Goes Awry. Is Human Monogamy Genetic? All Machine and No Ghost. Slower Reading for Better Philosophy.

Why We Need Public Philosophy. FrancisOnFilm: Cezanne et Moi. Art, Origins, and the Fearless Girl. Why Vote? Tricks for Political Persuasion. A Virtual Walden's Pond. Transcending Intersectionality. Foucault's Concept of Power. Aesthetics for Dogs? Muscles and Marxism. Some Thoughts on Problematic Arguments.

FrancisOnFilm: Get Out. Getting from Space and Time to Space-time. Space, Time, and Space-time. Cruelty in American Politics. Descartes, Elisabeth, and My Left Foot. Take the Mirror Test. Queer and Christian? So Did Plato. Art and Obscenity. To 'Get' a Piece of Art? Maybe 20 Minutes. A Country is a Country. Why Is Analytic Philosophy Dominant? Is Milo Really a Conservative? Free Speech on Campus. Are Self-Help Books Useless?

The Responsibility of Intellectuals. The Philosophical Dimensions of Reparations. Ask a Comedian. Arendt on Totalitarianism. How to Honor Black History Month. Philosophy Behind Bars. In Defense of Polyamory. The Case For and Against Reparations. RIP Bharati Mukherjee.

The Emperor Has No Philosophy. Deadly Thought Experiments. Confessions of a Cassandra. FrancisOnFilm: Authenticity at Sundance.

FrancisOnFilm: What is a Documentary? Stanley Cavell and Public Philosophy. Ta-Nehisi Coates Reflects on Obama. Hail to the Chief of Philosophy. Outrage or Pity? The Value of a College Education. Empathy for Deplorables? Introducing: Francis on Film. Derek Parfit. December Against Santa. The Examined Year Triumph and Defeat.

Is Donald Trump Lying or Bullshitting? The Mystery of the Multiverse. The Dark Side of the Cosmos. Trust and Mistrust. Dewey's Democracy. Magical Thinking. Do Religions Deserve Special Status?

Election Special — Uncut. Dangerous Demographics. Neuroaesthetics - Your Brain on Art. A Big Bang Blog. The Philosophy of Puns.

The Mystery of Music. Identity Politics. Struggles of Democracy. The Limits of Self Knowledge. Stagehands in the Theatre of Life. The Philanthropy Trap. Sleeping, Dreaming, and the Well-Lived Life. Dream Incubation Instructions.

Life as a Work of Art. The Moral Lives of Animals. Altered States of Consciousness. Lessons from the Trolley Problem. How Many Children? Memes and the Evolution of Culture. Ancient Wisdom for Modern Times. Why Does Anything Exist? Oneness is a Mystery.

Extreme Altruism. People with Guns. Freedom, rights and technology Why Free Software is Important. Gun Control. The Science of Happiness.

The Ancient Cosmos. Simone de Beauvoir. The Debt Crisis. Are we a white supremacist nation? Finding Meaning in a Material World. Justice Scalia and Judicial Diversity. White Privilege and Racial Injustice. Freedom and Free Markets. Religion and the Art of Living. Nations and Borders. The Divine Shape Shifter. Sartre's Existentialism. Life and Death in Prison. The Examined Year: - Uncut. Good, Evil, and the Divine Plan. Two Concepts of Safe Space. Self and Self-Presentation.

Gun violence, advocacy, and the NRA. Perception, Memory, and Justice. The Demands of Morality. Will Innovation Kill Us?

A Nietzschean Defense of Ben Carson. Collective Immortality: Living on Through Others. What is Cultural Appropriation? The Logic of Regret. Social media, knowledge of others, and self-knoweldge. Bioethics — Myths and Realities. Dance as a Way of Knowing. Technological Immortality. What is a Culture of Victimhood? The Changing Face of Feminism. Ashley Madison, accommodation, and silencing. The Ethics of Drone Warfare. Has Science Replaced Philosophy? Education and the Culture Wars.

Are Some People Better than Others? The Last "Universal Genius". The Fine-Tuning Argument for God. Does Science Advance? The Power and Perils of Satire. Does Neuroscience Threaten Free Will? The Ethics of Whistleblowing. Science and Politics: Friends or Foes? The Paradoxes of Ideology. Why Propaganda Matters.

Unconditional Love. When Democracies Torture. The Bone that Changed China. A new multi-level hierarchy of ethics and morality. The Nature of Wilderness. The McDonalds-ification of Education. Democracy in Crisis. Forbidden Words. Ethical Relativism. Disorders of the Mind - The Philosophy of Psychiatry. The More Good the Better? Camus and Absurdity. The Evolution of Storytelling.

Political Activism in the Digital Age. The Psychology of Climate Change Denial. Regulating Bodies. Food Justice. Could Race be in Your Genes? Categorizing Humans. December The Sex Trade.

Violating the Humanity of Others. Gut Feelings. Immortality: Hume and Boswell. The Moral Costs of Climate Change. Transformative Experiences. Identities Lost and Found in a Global Age. Intuitions Are a Guide to…Look Here!

The Fairness Fixation. Philosophy as Therapy. Freedom, Blame, and Resentment. Corporations and the Future of Democracy. Second-Guessing Ourselves. Babies and the Birth of Morality. Neuroscience and the Law. Is Intuition a Guide to Truth? Remixing Reality: Art and Literature for the 21st Century.

The Race Delusion. Privacy and The New Surveillance Society. Tainted by the Sins of Our Fathers? Anatomy of a Terrorist. The Problem of Other Minds. Being Human is Like Being Here. The Reality of Time. The Metaphysics of Color. Risk and Rationality. Conspiracy Theories. Weapons of Mass Destruction. Acting Together. Science and Gender. Inspiration for Evil.

The Legacy of Freud. Memory and the Self. Moral Luck. An Anti-Determinist Argument. Confessions of a Conflicted Carnivore. The Ethics of Soda. Tennis as a Way of Knowing. A New Wrinkle on an Old Problem. The Dark Side of Science. Latin-American Philosophy.

Diogenes the Cynic. Richard Fletcher, Historian. My Discovery of the X-Files. Science, Philosophy, and Theology. The George W. Bush Presidential Library and Museum.

Teaching Philosophy. What is philosophy? The Psychology of Partisan Politics. The Self. The Linguistics of Name Calling. December Turbo-charging the Mind. How Fiction Shapes Us.

Economics: Cult or Science? Mind Reading. Poetry As a Way of Knowing. Epicurus and the Good Life. On Being Normal. The Dionysus Awards. Black Solidarity. The Right to Privacy. Philosophy in Fiction. Is Democracy a Universal Value? The Examined Year: December Nihilism and Meaning. What would Jesus do? A Blog for Christmas.

Is it wrong to wreck the earth? To Forgive and Forget. The Military: What is it Good for? Is Nothing Sacred Anymore? Thinking Inside the Box. Cooperation and Conflict. From the Minds of Babies. Morality and the Self. War, Sacrifice, and the Media. Deconstructing the College Admissions Rat Race. It is very natural to resent when one is wronged, and the demand for payback or retribution, which is in my view the most problematic aspect of anger, probably has an evolutionary basis.

It is, in short, deeply human. Punishment of some type may be useful for the future, by deterring wrongdoing and reforming offenders. Anger is also seen as the emotion that jolts us towards social justice.



0コメント

  • 1000 / 1000